Emanuelis Levinas (later adapted to French orthography as Emmanuel
Levinas) received a traditional Jewish education in Lithuania. After WWII, he
studied the Talmud under the
enigmatic "Monsieur Chouchani,"
whose influence he acknowledged only late in his life.
Levinas began his philosophical studies at Strasbourg University in 1924,
where he began his lifelong friendship with the French philosopher Maurice Blanchot. In 1928, he
went to Freiburg University to
study phenomenology under Edmund Husserl. At Freiburg
he also met Martin Heidegger.
Levinas became one of the very first French intellectuals to draw attention to
Heidegger and Husserl, by translating Husserl's Cartesian Meditations and by
drawing on their ideas in his own philosophy, in works such as his The
Theory of Intuition in Husserl’s Phenomenology, De
l'Existence à l'Existant, and En Découvrant
l’existence avec Husserl et Heidegger.
According to his New York Times obituary, Levinas came
to regret his enthusiasm for Heidegger, because of the latter's Nazism. During
a lecture on forgiveness, Levinas stated "One can forgive many Germans,
but there are some Germans it is difficult to forgive. It is difficult to
forgive Heidegger."[1]
After earning his doctorate Levinas taught at a private Jewish High School
in Paris, the École Normale Israélite Orientale, eventually becoming its
director. He began teaching at the University of Poitiers in 1961, at the
Nanterre campus of the University of Paris in 1967, and at the Sorbonne in 1973, from
which he retired in 1979. He was also a Professor at the University of Fribourg
in Switzerland.
In the 1950s, Levinas emerged from the circle of intellectuals surrounding Jean Wahl as a leading
French thinker. His work is based on the ethics of the Other or, in Levinas' terms, on "ethics
as first philosophy." For Levinas, the Other is not knowable and cannot be
made into an object of the self, as is done by traditional metaphysics (which Levinas
called "ontology"). Levinas prefers to think of philosophy as the
"wisdom of love" rather than the love of wisdom (the literal Greek
meaning of the word "philosophy"). By his lights, ethics becomes an
entity independent of subjectivity to the point where ethical responsibility is
integral to the subject; hence an ethics of responsibility precedes any
"objective searching after truth."
Levinas derives the primacy of his ethics from the experience of the
encounter with the Other. For Levinas, the irreducible relation, the epiphany,
of the face-to-face, the encounter
with another, is a privileged phenomenon in which the other person's proximity
and distance are both strongly felt. "The Other precisely reveals
himself in his alterity not in a shock
negating the I, but as the primordial phenomenon of gentleness."[2]. At the same
time, the revelation of the face makes a demand, this demand is before one can
express, or know one's freedom, to affirm or deny.[3] One instantly
recognizes the transcendence and heteronomy of the Other. Even murder fails as
an attempt to take hold of this otherness.
In Levinas's later thought following "Totality and Infinity", he
argued that our responsibility for the other was already rooted within our
subjective constitution. It should be noted that the first line of the preface
of this book is "everyone will readily agree that it is of the highest
importance to know whether we are not duped by morality."[4] This can be
seen most clearly in his later account of recurrence (chapter 4 in
"Otherwise Than Being"), where Levinas maintained that subjectivity
was formed in and through our subjected-ness to the other. In this way, his
effort was not to move away from traditional attempts to locate the other
within subjectivity (this he agrees with), so much as his view was that
subjectivity was primordially ethical and not theoretical. That is to say, our
responsibility for the other was not a derivative feature of our subjectivity;
instead, obligation founds our subjective being-in-the-world by giving it a
meaningful direction and orientation. Levinas's thesis "ethics as first
philosophy", then, means that the traditional philosophical pursuit of knowledge
is but a secondary feature of a more basic ethical duty to the other.
The elderly Levinas was a distinguished French public intellectual, whose
books reportedly sold well. He had a major impact on the young Jacques Derrida, a fellow
French Jew whose seminal Writing and Difference contains an
essay, "Violence and Metaphysics," on Levinas. Derrida also delivered
a eulogy at Levinas's funeral, later published as Adieu à Emmanuel Levinas, an
appreciation and exploration of Levinas's moral philosophy. Here, Derrida
followed Bracha L. Ettinger's
interpretation of Levinas's notion of femininity and transformed his own
earlier reading of this subject accordingly.[5]
Levinas became a naturalized French citizen in 1930. When France declared war on Germany, he was
ordered to report for military duty. During the German invasion of France in 1940, his military unit was quickly surrounded and
forced to surrender. Levinas spent the rest of World War II as a prisoner
of war in a camp near Hannover in Germany. Levinas was
assigned to a special barracks for Jewish prisoners, who were forbidden any
forms of religious worship. Life in the camp was as difficult as might be
expected, with Levinas often forced to chop wood and do other menial tasks.
Other prisoners saw him frequently jotting in a notebook. These jottings became
his book De l'existence à l'existant (1947) and a
series of lectures published under the title Le Temps et l'Autre
(1948).
Meanwhile, Maurice Blanchot helped
Levinas' wife and daughter spend the war in a monastery, thus sparing them the
Holocaust. Blanchot, at considerable personal risk, also saw to it that Levinas
was able to keep in contact with his immediate family through letters and other
messages. Other members of Levinas' family were not so fortunate; his
mother-in-law was deported and never heard from again, while his father and
brothers were murdered in Lithuania by the Nazi SS
First published Sun Jul 23, 2006; substantive revision
Sun Mar 18, 2007
Levinas's philosophy has been called ethics. If ethics means rationalist
self-legislation and freedom (deontology), the calculation of happiness
(utilitarianism), or the cultivation of virtues (virtue ethics), then Levinas's
philosophy is not an ethics. Levinas claimed, in 1961, that he was developing a
“first philosophy.” This first philosophy is neither traditional logic nor
metaphysics, however.[1] It
is an interpretive, phenomenological description of the rise and repetition of
the face-to-face encounter, or the intersubjective relation at its precognitive
core; viz., being called by another and responding to that other. If
precognitive experience, that is, human sensibility, can be characterized
conceptually, then it must be described in what is most characteristic to it: a
continuum of sensibility and affectivity, in other words, sentience and emotion
in their interconnection.[2]
This entry will focus on Levinas's philosophy, rather than his
Talmudic lessons (see the bibliography) and his essays on Judaism (notably, Difficult
Freedom: Essays on Judaism, 1963). Levinas's philosophical
project can be called constructivist. He proposes phenomenological description
and a hermeneutics of lived experience in the world. He lays bare levels of
experience described neither by Husserl nor by Heidegger. These layers of
experience concern the encounter with the world, with the human other, and a
reconstruction of a layered interiority characterized by sensibility and
affectivity.
Jacques Derrida pointed out in 1967 that “Levinas does not want to propose
laws or moral rules…it is a matter of [writing] an ethics of ethics.”[3] An
ethics of ethics means, here, the exploration of conditions of possibility of
any interest in good actions or lives. In light of that, it can be said that
Levinas is not writing an ethics at all. Instead, he is exploring the meaning
of intersubjectivity and lived immediacy in light of three themes:
transcendence, existence, and the human other. These three themes structure the
present entry.
At the core of Levinas's mature thought (i.e., works of 1961 and 1974) are
descriptions of the encounter with another person. That encounter evinces a
particular feature: the other impacts me unlike any worldly object or force. I
can constitute the other person cognitively, on the basis of vision, as an alter
ego. I can see that another human being is “like me,” acts like me,
appears to be the master of her conscious life. That was Edmund Husserl's basic
phenomenological approach to constituting other people within a shared social
universe. But Husserl's constitution lacks, Levinas argues, the core element of
intersubjective life: the other person addresses me, calls to me. He does not
even have to utter words in order for me to feel the summons implicit
in his approach. It is this encounter that Levinas describes and approaches
from multiple perspectives (e.g., internal and external). He will present it as
fully as it is possible to introduce an affective event into everyday language
without turning it into an intellectual theme. Beyond any other philosophical
concerns, the fundamental intuition of Levinas's philosophy is the
non-reciprocal relation of responsibility. In the mature thought this
responsibility is transcendence par excellence and has a temporal
dimension specific to it as human experience.
The phenomenological descriptions of intersubjective responsibility are
built upon an analysis of living in the world. These are unique to Levinas.
They differ from Heidegger's analytic of existence. For Levinas, an ‘I’ lives
out its embodied existence according to modalities. It consumes the fruits of
the world. It enjoys and suffers from the natural elements. It constructs
shelters and dwellings. It carries on the social and economic transactions of
its daily life. Yet, no event is as affectively disruptive for a consciousness
holding sway in its world than the encounter with another person. In this
encounter (even if it later becomes competitive or instrumental), the ‘I’ first
experiences itself as called and liable to account for itself. It responds. The
‘I’'s response is as if to a nebulous command. Nothing says that the other gave
a de facto command. The command or summons is part of the intrinsic
relationality. With the response comes the beginning of language as dialogue.
The origin of language, for Levinas, is always response—a
responding-to-another, that is, to her summons. Dialogue arises ultimately
through that response. Herein lie the roots of intersubjectivity as lived
immediacy. Levinas has better terms for it: responsibility is the affective, immediate
experience of “transcendence” and “fraternity.” We will return to these themes.
The intersubjective origin of discourse and fraternity can only be reached
by phenomenological description. Otherwise, it is deduced from principles that
have long since been abstracted from the immediacy of the face-to-face
encounter with the other. Levinas's descriptions show that ‘in the beginning
was the human relation’. The primacy of relation explains why it is that human
beings are interested in the questions of ethics at all. But for that reason,
Levinas has made interpretative choices. To situate first philosophy in the
face-to-face encounter is to choose to begin philosophy not with the world, not
with God, but with what will be argued to be the prime condition for human
communication. For this reason, Levinas's first philosophy starts from an
interpretive phenomenology. Like Husserl's, his first philosophy sets aside
empirical prejudices about subjects and objects. Like Husserl's phenomenology,
it strips away accumulated layers of conceptualization, in order to reveal
experience as it comes to light. For Levinas, intersubjective experience, as it
comes to light, proves ‘ethical’ in the simple sense that an ‘I’ discovers its
own particularity when it is singled out by the gaze of the other. This gaze is
interrogative and imperative. It says “do not kill me.” It also implores the ‘I’,
who eludes it only with difficulty, although this request may have actually no
discursive content. This command and supplication occurs because human faces
impact us as affective moments or, what Levinas calls ‘interruptions’. The face
of the other is firstly expressiveness. It could be compared to a force. We
must, of course, use everyday language to translate these affective interruptions.
Therein lie difficulties that this entry will clarify.
Suffice it to say that first philosophy is responsibility that unfolds into
dialogical sociality. It is also Levinas's unique way of defining transcendence
in relation to the world and to what Heidegger called Being. Throughout this
entry, we will refer to the themes of transcendence and Being in light of the
work of Husserl and Heidegger. It is Levinas's project to uncover the layers of
pre-intellectual (what Husserl called pre-intentional or objectless
intentionality), affective experience in which transcendence comes to pass.
Thus, the phenomenological descriptions that Levinas adapts from Husserl and
Heidegger extend both of their approaches. However, Levinas's particular
extension of Husserl and Heidegger unfolds over the course of an entire
philosophical career. For that reason, this entry will follow that career
chronologically, as it evolves. We will emphasize, in what follows, how it is
that Levinas's thought is: (1) a unique first philosophy; (2) not a traditional
ethics (neither virtue, nor utilitarian, nor deontological ethics); (3) the
investigation of the lived conditions of possibility of any de facto
human interest in ethics; (4) a highly original adaptation of phenomenology and
the interpretation of pre-intentional embodied existence (viz., descriptions of
sensibility and affectivity).
1906 |
Born
January 12 in Kaunas (or Kovno, in Russian), Lithuania. Lithuania is a part
of pre-Revolutionary Russia in which the then surrounding culture ‘tolerates’
Jews. He is the eldest child in a middle class family and has two brothers,
Boris and Aminadab. |
1914 |
In the
wake of the War, Levinas's family emigrates to Karkhov, in the Ukraine. The
family returns to Lithuania in 1920, two years after the country obtains
independence from the Revolutionary government. |
1923 |
Goes to
study philosophy in Strasbourg (France). Levinas studies philosophy with
Maurice Pradines, psychology with Charles Blondel, and sociology with Maurice
Halbwachs. He meets Maurice Blanchot who will become a close friend. |
1928-29 |
Levinas
travels to Freiburg to study with Edmund Husserl; he attends Heidegger's
seminar. |
1930 |
Publishes
his thesis in French, The Theory of Intuition in Husserl's Phenomenology. |
1931 |
French
translation, by Levinas, of Husserl's Sorbonne lectures, Cartesian
Meditations, in collaboration with Gabrielle Peiffer. |
1932 |
He
marries Raïssa Levi, whom he had known since childhood. |
1934 |
Levinas
publishes a philosophical analysis of “Hitlerism,” Reflections on the
Philosophy of Hitlerism. |
1935 |
Levinas
publishes an original essay in hermeneutic ontology, On Escape, in
the Émile Bréhier's journal Recherches philosophiques (reprinted in
1982). |
1939 |
Naturalized
French; enlists in the French officer corps. |
1940 |
Captured
by the Nazis; imprisoned in Fallingsbotel, a labor camp for
officers. His Lithuanian family is murdered. His wife Raïssa, and daughter,
Simone, are hidden by religious in Orléans. |
1947 |
Following
the publication of Existence and Existents (which Levinas began
writing in captivity), and Time and the Other that regrouped four
lectures given at the Collège Philosophique (founded by Jean Wahl), Levinas
becomes Director of the École Normale Israélite Orientale, Paris. |
1949 |
After the
death of their second daughter, Andrée Éliane, Levinas and his wife have a
son, Michael, who becomes a pianist and a composer. |
1957 |
He
delivers his first Talmudic readings at the Colloque des Intellectuels juifs
de Langue française. A colloquium attended by Vladimir Jankélévitch, André
Neher, and Jean Halpérin, among others. |
1961 |
Publishes
his doctorate (ès Lettres), Totality and Infinity: An Essay on
Exteriority. Position at the Université de Poitiers. |
1963 |
Publishes
Difficult Freedom: Essays on Judaism. |
1967 |
Professor
at the Université de Paris, Nanterre, with Paul Ricœur. |
1968 |
Publishes
Quatres lectures talmudiques (English translation in Nine
Talmudic Readings). |
1972 |
Humanism
of the Other. |
1973 |
Lecture
at the Université de Paris IV-Sorbonne. |
1974 |
Otherwise
than Being, or Beyond Essence, the second magnum opus. |
1975 |
Sur
Maurice Blanchot
(no English translation). |
1976 |
Proper
Names. |
1977 |
Du
sacré au saint
(English translation in Nine Talmudic Readings). |
1982 |
Of
God Who Comes to Mind, Beyond the Verse and the radio conversations with Philippe
Nemo, Ethics and Infinity. |
1984 |
Transcendance
et Intelligibilité
(English translation in Emmanuel Levinas: Basic Philosophical Writings) |
1987 |
Outside
the Subject, a
collection of texts, old and new on philosophers, language, and politics. |
1988 |
In
the Time of the Nations. |
1990 |
De
l'oblitération: Entretien avec Françoise Armengaud (no English translation); a
discussion about the sculpture of fellow Lithuanian, Sasha Sosno. |
1991 |
Entre
Nous: On Thinking-of-the-Other. An issue of the prestigious Les Cahiers de L'Herne
is dedicated to Levinas's work. |
1993 |
Sorbonne
lectures of 1973-74, published as God, Death, and Time. The annual
colloquium at Cerisy-la-Salle publishes a volume devoted to him. |
1994 |
Raïssa
Levinas dies in September. Levinas publishes a collection of essays, Liberté
et commandement (no English translation) and Unforeseen History,
edited by Pierre Hayat. |
1995 |
Alterity and Transcendence. |
1996 |
New
Talmudic Readings
(published posthumously). |
1998 |
Éthique
comme philosophie première (no English translation, published posthumously). |
Levinas published his thesis, The Theory of Intuition in Husserl's
Phenomenology in 1930. It was the first book-length introduction to
Husserl's thought in French. By privileging the theme of intuition, Levinas
established what German speaking readers would have found in Husserl's Ideas
(published 1913): every human experience is open to phenomenological
description; every human experience is from the outset meaningful and can be
approached as a mode of intentionality.[4]
The following year, he published a translation of Husserl's Cartesian
Meditations, in which the latter laid out a systematic presentation of
transcendental phenomenology.[5] In
the 1930s, Levinas continue to publish studies of the thought of his two
principal teachers, Husserl and Heidegger. These included “Martin Heidegger and
Ontology”[6]
and the comprehensive “The Work of Edmund Husserl.”[7] In
the 1930s and 40s, his philosophical project is influenced by Husserl's
phenomenological method, which turned around the centrality of the “transcendental
ego.” However, suspicious of an excessive intellectualism in Husserl's approach
to essences, Levinas embraced the concrete, worldly approach to existence in
Heidegger's Being and Time.[8]
Between 1930 and 1935, he will nevertheless turn away from Heidegger's approach
to Being and transcendence and develop the outlines of a counter-ontology. He
will reconceive transcendence as a need for escape, and work out a new logic of
lived time in that project.
Levinas's first experimental essay, On Escape (De l'évasion,
1935), examined the relationship between the embodied (sentient) self and the
intentional ego,[9]
from the perspectives of physical and affective states, including need,
pleasure, shame, and nausea. In this original philosophical exercise, Levinas
revisited Heidegger's approach to time and transcendence.[10] He
was less concerned than was Heidegger with the question of existence that opens
up before us when, beset by profound anxiety, we experience the ‘dissolving’ of
things in the world. Levinas's question was not: “Why is there Being instead of
simply nothing?” His concern was to approach Being differently, through the
(human) being for which the primary experiences of Being are of its
embodied, but not physiological, existence. Unlike Heidegger, Levinas's
approach gave priority to embodiment and its lived “moods,” as well as to
humans' failed attempts to get away from the being that we ourselves are. “Escape,”
he wrote, “is the need to get out of oneself, that is, to break that most
radical and unalterably binding of chains, the fact that the I [moi]
is oneself [soi-même].”[11] In
the two, crossing dimensions of human life, sentient-affective and intentional,
our experience of Being comes to pass.
Levinas's early project approached transcendence in light of humans'
irreducible urge to get past the limits of their physical and social
situations. His transcendence is less transcendence-in-the-world than
transcendence through and because of sensibility. This approach to
transcendence as evasion poses the question of mortality, finite being, and so,
infinity.
Levinas accepted Heidegger's arguments that a human being experiences
itself as if cast into its world,[12]
without control over its beginning and ending. Heidegger's human being, or Dasein,
lives out its time projecting itself toward diverse possibilities, and may
confront its own mortality in this way. The projective element of
transcendence, which Heidegger described in The Basic Problems of
Phenomenology[13] as
simply a “stepping over to…as such,” was of interest to Levinas. But he would
enquire: to what are we ‘stepping over’? And from what are we ‘stepping over’?
Levinas writes:
And yet modern sensibility wrestles with problems that
indicate…the abandonment of this concern with transcendence. As if it had the
certainty that the idea of the limit could not apply to the existence
of what is…and as if modern sensibility perceived in being a defect still more
profound (OE, 51).
The objection Levinas raised against Heidegger's transcendence was not that
it rejected theology. Rather, it was that ‘stepping over’, or being out ahead
of oneself, suggested that Being, as Heidegger understood it, was finite or
somehow flawed. That places Being in a cultural and historical context,[14]
or, to put it more philosophically, it poses the question of the meaning of the
finite and the infinite; that is, the question of the “idea of the limit.”
Levinas asks: “[Is] the need for escape not the exclusive matter of a finite
being?…Would an infinite being have the need to take leave of itself?” We are
admittedly finite. But how do we know this, and from what perspective do we
contemplate Being as finite? “Is this infinite being not precisely the ideal of
self-sufficiency and the promise of eternal contentment?” (OE, 56). The
decision about the ultimate meaning of the infinite is not made in the 1935
essay. It returns as a theme in the 1940s essays, however. Important here are:
(1) Levinas's argument that Heidegger's conception of existence is historically
specific. (2) To be embodied is to struggle with the limits of one's facticity and
one's situation, and it is here that the question of Being first arises.
If Heidegger's Dasein confronted the question of Being by finding
itself brought before itself in anxiety, Levinas proposes other ways by which
the gap narrows between Being itself and the beings that we are. Following the leitmotif
of our irrepressible need to escape, Levinas examines a host of attempted and
disappointed transcendences: need, pleasure, shame, and nausea. In these
possibilities, the corporeal self is posited, set down as a substance, in its
existence. Unlike Heidegger's Being, these states are not abstract. Here begins
Levinas's protracted insistence that Being is continuous presence, not, as
Heidegger insisted, an event of disclosure and withdrawal.
From the outset, the “fact of existing” refers to concrete human existence.
In identifying existence as firstly human, Levinas establishes that Heidegger's
Being, or the “being of that which is,” answers a formal ontological question,
to which determinations like finiteness and infinity, not to mention escape and
transcendence, apply only vaguely. He will therefore concentrate on what it
means for a human being to posit itself, in an act that is
not already abstracted from its everyday life.
Affective self-positing, not Heidegger's Dasein with its projective
temporality, would offer the purest and most concrete access possible to our
finite existence. I am my joy or my pain, if provisionally. Our
diverse attempts to get out of our everyday situations are not the same as
projections toward new possibilities, where our death lies behind all the
others (death is the ultimate limit, or “possibility of impossibility,” for
Heidegger). Escape represents, for Levinas, a positive, dynamic need. But needs
are not equivalent to mere suffering. Within many needs is the anticipation of
their fulfillment. If need, whether for sustenance or diversion, cannot assure
an enduring transcendence of everyday existence, it nevertheless beckons and
enriches us, even if it can sometimes be experienced as oppressive. In this
youthful work, Levinas thus rethinks need in light of fullness rather than
privation, as was commonly done. In so doing, he opens a different
understanding of existence itself. Whether it is experienced by pleasure or
suffering, need is the ground of our existence. That means that transcendence,
in Levinas's understanding of it, is continually directed toward “something
other than ourselves” (OE, 58). And it suggests that the deep motivation of
need is to get out of the being that we ourselves are—our situation and
our embodiment. In 1935, Levinas's counter-ontology moves Heidegger's Being
toward the unified duality of sentient self and intentional ‘I’, here and now,
not projected toward its ultimate disappearance in death
Reconceived as need, pleasure, or even nausea, transcendence gives us
access to a temporality that is neither Aristotle's “measure of motion,” nor
the fullness of awaiting (the kairos or moment in the early
Heidegger). Pleasure and pain are intensities: “something like abysses, ever
deeper, into which our existence…hurls itself” (OE, 61). The priority of the
present, concentrated into an extended moment is opened up through sensibility
and affectivity. In pleasure as in pain, we need—not out of lack—but
in desire or in hope. “Pleasure is…nothing less than a
concentration in the instant…” (OE, 61). The present thus receives existential
priority over Heidegger's projections of lived temporality. Levinas's emphasis
on the embodied present is a theme he never abandons.[15] In
as much as he received it from Husserl, he will vastly enrich it.[16]
In sum, Levinas's early project is structured around the reconceptualization
of fundamental existential categories. If Husserl's transcendental ego[17]
returns, here, as the ‘I’ of conscious intentions, which Levinas
differentiated from the self of embodiment, it remains the case that
the embodied self holds priority, precisely as the site from which
transcendence first arises. If the ‘self’ and ‘I’ duality is where the
positivity of Being is clearest, then the precedence of the world and of Being
is necessarily displaced. On the other hand, Heidegger's finite Being, which he
understood as disclosure and withdrawal, is interpreted in a pre-Heideggerian
fashion, as constant presence. That presence is modalized through our manifold
sensations, emotions and states of mind.
In 1935, Levinas was convinced that through sensation and states of mind,
we discover both the need to escape ourselves and the futility of getting out
of existence. In the physical torment of nausea, we experience Being in its
simplest, most oppressive neutrality. To this, Levinas adds three provocative
themes. First, a being that seeks to escape itself, because it finds itself
trapped in its own facticity, is not a master, but a “creature” (OE, 72).
Second, nausea is not simply a physiological event. If nausea shows us,
dramatically, how existence encircles us on all sides, to the point of
submerging us, then social and political actuality can also nauseate. Third, if
Being is experienced in its pure form as neutrality and impotence, then we can
neither bypass Being (following the “aspirations of Idealism” [OE, 73]), nor
accept it passively. Being is existence, but it is our existence. The
mark of our existence is need, or the non-acceptance of neutral Being. In 1935,
Levinas concludes, “Every civilization that accepts being—with the tragic
despair it contains and the crimes it justifies—merits the name ‘barbarian’,”
(OE, 73). The question remains: How shall we conceptualize a sensuous need to
transcend Being? Embodied need is not an illusion; but is transcendence one?
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/levinas/#LifCar